Activists as Knowledge Workers9.doc

Activists as Knowledge Workers9.doc
      74 KB   politicstahl   Mar 24, 2007
Activists as Knowledge Workers 
 
 
 
Activists as Knowledge Workers
by

Donald E. Stahl

I: Types of Resistance



Nothing strikes the student of public opinion and democracy more forcefully than the paucity of information most people possess about politics.”John A. Ferejohn (“Information and the Electoral Process,” in John A. Ferejohn and James H. Kuklinski, (edd.), Information and Democratic Processes, (U. of Illinois Press, 1990), p. 3) “…most political information is too costly and of too little use for most of us to bother to try to acquire it.” (p. 13). “Political institutions are an expression of the division of labor: they permit small numbers of officials to regulate and direct social processes without having to consult regularly with the rest of us. In this sense, political institutions economize on the distribution and processing of information. We elect officials to learn about things that might affect us and then to act on our behalf as we would if we had the same information.” (p. 6.)

The two simplest truths I know about the distribution of political information in modern electorates are that the mean is low and the variance is high.” Phillip E. Converse, “Popular Representation and the Distribution of Information.” (op. cit., p. 372).

In the Knowledge Society, it is imperative that we learn how to make sure that the right information gets to the right people at the right time in the right form.”Keith Devlin, Infosense: Turning Information into Knowledge, ( Freeman, 2001, p. 199).

After spending the better part of the last five years treating these theories with utmost skepticism, I have devoted serious time to actually studying them in recent months, and have also carefully watched several videos that are available on the subject. I have come to believe that significant parts of the 9/11 theories are true, and that therefore significant parts of the ‘official story’ put out by the U.S. government and the 9/11 Commission are false.”Bill Christison, former Director of CIA's Office of Regional and Political Analysis, Dissident Voice, 14 August 2006.



As Converse says in the quote above, it is a truism of political science that not many people are interested in politics, but those who are tend to be very interested. They are what Converse in a previous, seminal article called ideologues and near-ideologues. Now, as I shall use the word ‘activist’ in this article, not all ideologues and near-ideologues are activists; i.e., not everyone who is very interested in politics is an activist. As the term ‘ideologue’ suggests, some people who are very interested in politics are less interested in propagating that interest among the relatively uninterested than they are in seeing to it that their fellow ideologues get things right. The former are what I shall here call activists; the latter may be researchers or theorists or planners or organizers or political correctors or connectors. Insofar as one addresses oneself to the uninterested one is an activist. Insofar as one addresses oneself to one’s fellow ideologues, one isn’t. In writing this article, I am not engaging in activism, since I am addressing only fellow 9/11 Truthers. This is a worthwhile thing to do, since we need to form an identifiable community in order to do what needs to be done, and a community can only be formed through mutual discussion, but it is not what I am here calling activism.

9/11 Truth, whatever its details turn out to be, is perfectly suited to activism, because it is a surefire way to make the vast uninterested majority interested, if only they can be brought believe it. It’s one thing to say, “Let George do it, I haven’t got time,” under ordinary circumstances, but it’s quite another thing to say “Let George do it,” when what he might do is kill your family, even for the best and most far-sighted of reasons. This is information that is certainly not “too costly and of too little use.”
.
We should not think we are going to change permanently “the distribution of political information” in modern society. That is impossible, simply because of what Ferejohn above describes as the division of labor with regard to information. That division of labor forces itself on our notice. Information overload necessitates information triage, and as activists our job is to make sure our information makes the cut. I think everyone would agree that we should use all the tools we can in order to do this, and that includes scholarly knowledge about the human psyche, the mass audience, and recent discoveries and theories about knowledge and its transmission in society.

Let us distinguish information avoidance, information rejection or disbelief, information gathering, and information accessibility. The more accessible information is, the less effort is necessary to acquire it.

Information overload forces us to avoid information constantly. Everyone with an email account knows this. We see who a message is from, or what it’s about, and we decide instantly, “I want to know more about this,” or “I don’t want to know more about this.” We try to ignore commercials on television. We look around the edges of ads in newspapers, trying to find a scrap of news. We block out information which we expect to be useless, distracting and time-wasting. We carry appointment books so that we don’t have to keep relatively trivial information salient in our minds. The average stay at a website is rumored to be three seconds.

I just recently learned that Dell invites its customers to return their used-up ink cartridges to them for recycling, postage-free. I had been simply throwing them in the trash, because when new cartridges arrived I had what I wanted, and didn’t bother to look at the printed matter that came with them, though it was in my hand. This was information of interest to me, and quite accessible, but until now unnoticed.

On the other hand, information which we need for our particular situation often must be sought in many places and assembled with considerable effort. Even information which we know to be physically close may be inaccessible. A telephone directory which carried all the entries of a conventional one but was not alphabetized would be useless, even though the listing you want is “right there.” Online, a search that returns a hundred or more URLs is really only giving you as many as you have time for, starting at the top.

Each person wants something different from their telephone directory, but even if everyone wants the same thing from a document it is still possible for that document to bury the information, by means of fine print, obscure language, and sheer prolixity. Since this is so, it is also possible to claim that a lengthy document contains all the information relevant to you when it does not. Sometimes, making such false claims possible is the purpose of creating the lengthy document. As every rabbit knows, in the United States’ climate, you have to dig your own rabbit hole.

In theory, information in a speaking human’s brain should be more accessible than it is in a voice messaging system. Whether you go looking for information, or information comes at you in an unwelcome flow, sorting through it is the problem. A certain minimum contact is necessary. In order to avoid ads we must know that they are ads, in order to avoid emails from a certain source we must know that they are from that sourceor our email provider must know.

Devlin’s claim about getting the right information to the right people at the right time in the right form is something that few people would explicitly disagree with, but which they habitually ignore, especially in the 9/11 Truth Movement. Our debates about what to do with our information are based on the assumption that one size fits all. In fact, two questions are crucial in delivering our message: how much time is going to be available for the reception of the message, and who is the intended recipient? We will return to this point shortly.

Chomsky and other left gatekeepers allege that no one has the time to become expert in all the fields pertaining to 9/11 Truth, and consequently 9/11 Truth is a waste of effort and a diversion from the supremely important task of opposing the forces of darkness. Ruppert says that it’s a mistake to concentrate on physical evidence because it always can and always will be opposed by as many experts as the other side can afford to pay, and no one has deeper pockets than the government. Whatever the personal psychology behind Chomsky’s stance, objectively it faces directly backward. No other tool could conceivably be as effective as 9/11 Truth in restructuring the world. Ruppert’s hard-earned disgust with expertise and technology ignores the facts that today no expert will challenge DNA evidence, the tobacco companies’ experts lost their war long ago, and. currently hired climatologists are in the process of wasting their employers’ money.

But handing someone a copy of Crossing the Rubicon and saying, “Here. Read this,” doesn’t work, because they just won’t do it. Sometimes, I know from experience, they won‘t look at videos either.

It is not that the relevant information is buried in Ruppert’s book. All of that volume is relevant to 9/11 Truth, and the picture it paints is essential to understanding, but it presupposes a commitment of time which simply is not going to be agreed to by very many people.

Catherine Z. Elgin's Considered Judgment (Princeton, 1996) has several features of interest to 9/11 activists. Some salient instances are her use as an example, "conspiracy theories about the assassination of President Kennedy" (p. 144), her recognition of the importance of emotion in the process of inquiry (pp. 146-169), and her discussions of Wittgenstein, Kuhn and Rorty, or what she calls "pure procedural epistemology" or "Knowledge by Consensus" (pp. 60-100), which more or less says that what is true is determined by common consent, since common consent determines what words mean. (One seems to encounter this position fairly often in broaching 9/11 Truth. Cf. Steven Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-century England,
( University of Chicago, 1995)).

But through the book another theme recurs which is of more direct significance for us, especially with regard to the tension between the strategy of using physical evidence, and the juridical approach which Ruppert adopts of pursuing means, motive and opportunity: the theme of composition and division of evidence: “connecting the dots.”


"Justification is holistic. Support for a conclusion comes not from a single line of argument but from a host of considerations of varying degrees of strength and relevance. Indirect evidence and weak arguments, which alone would bear little weight, may be interwoven into a fabric that strongly supports a conclusion. Each element derives warrant from its place in the whole." (p. 130).
"In forging connections among initially tenable claims, we integrate them into a mutually supportive network. This enhances their tenability, each being more reasonable in light of the others than it was alone. It also confers tenability on the sentences we annex, transforming initially doubtful claims into integral parts of an acceptable system of thought." (p. 104).
"It [constructionalism] can adopt considerations too poorly supported for perfect procedural epistemologies to countenance, secure in the knowledge that unwise admissions can later be rescinded. ... It requires weak reasons to be more tightly woven into the fabric of commitments than strong ones. But it allows that this can be done, that collective action can compensate for individual shortcomings. A constellation of weak reasons sometimes
constitutes a strong case." (p. 121).


All this is tremendously plausible, and it highlights for us the important fact that a strategy for activism proceeding via this avenue is hobbled by having to use a multitude of different considerations. It takes time, patience and memory to come to a position from which one can say, “ALL these things can’t be coincidences.” PR and other advertising professionals have long known that mass audiences do not sit still long enough for very much information to be brought into play; and we have long known that individuals do not have much patience for what they do not want to hear.

Resistance to 9/11 Truth comes in different degrees, and it would seem to be measurable by how little time someone is willing to give it.

Those who are willing to accept free DVDs will probably look at them (and those who buy them certainly will), but those who are only asked to look at something, whether a book or an internet site, may or may not do it. Without a physical object as a reminder, a promise is quickly forgotten, just as a statement of fact, without some visible corroboration, is quickly discounted.

However, there are opponents of 9/11 Truth who are almost as much motivated as we are. They nit-pick, name-call and publish wherever they can, even counter-demonstrate and make videos. They are familiar with many of the facts of 9/11, but deny their significance. For these individuals, it is not how little time they spend on 9/11 Truth that measures the strength of their resistance, but how much.

And even knowing how much resistance there is doesn’t tell you where that resistance is coming from. Knowing a little bit about types and sources of resistance can be helpful in avoiding premature generalizations and the unnecessary discouragement they can bring. I shall now describe five different sources of such resistance, some of them far more important than others. These facts help us identify different audiences, and frame our messagesor seek different audiencesaccordingly.

The first, least important source, I shall briefly describe like this: no matter how good a magician you are, if you show a card trick to your dog, he will not be surprised. That is neither your fault nor his. If he is not a member of your audience, he is still a valuable member of your family.

The second and third sources of resistance are the most prominent. I shall introduce them via some quotations having to do with the psychological process of defense, either in general or in some specific form. Cardinal Caraffa said to his uncle, Pope Paul IV, “Populus vult decipi. Decipiatur.” The people wish to be deceived. Let them be deceived. As Truthers, we say instead, “Let them be undeceived.” To do anything else would be to join those whom Dr. M. Scott Peck has called, “the people of the lie.”

The process of defense nearly always utilizes two tendencies analogous to flight and the erection of barricades.” “It is important to remember that all defenses operate automatically and outside of awareness. Defenses are motivated, but they are not executed voluntarily. The average person does not know what defenses he is using, nor can he voluntarily stop using a defense if its presence is pointed out to him.” “The basic empirical evidence of repression is an inappropriate under-reaction to a relevant situation and indirect evidence that the repressed tendencies are actually present.”

I think most people have by now heard that there are some who maintain that the USG was complicit in 9/11. Some of them wonder about why those individuals maintain that, but don’t know much about why they would have gotten the idea, i.e., they know only what they have been told by the media. People like this, who have minimal information about 9/11 Truth, may be so either because they simply haven’t been exposed to anything more, or because they have exerted some small degree of effort, like Chomsky, not to be exposed to it.

Those who are innocent of 9/11 Knowledge and intend to remain that way are very likely to be what Bob Altemeyer has forever named Right-Wing Authoritarians. George Lakoff explains (in Moral Politics) how RWAs have come to have the political power they now have, and John Dean (in Conservatives without Conscience) explains that Lakoff in his book is talking about Altemeyer’s work.

By “Right-Wing Authoritarianism” Altemeyer means:

“…the covariation of three attitudinal clusters in a person:

1. Authoritarian submissiona high degree of submission to the authorities who are perceived to be established and legitimate in the society in which one lives.
2. Authoritarian aggressiona general aggressiveness, directed against various persons, that is perceived to be sanctioned by established authorities.
3. Conventionalisma high degree of adherence to the social conventions that are perceived to be endorsed by society and its established authorities.”


When Hayek denied that he was a conservative he probably meant, avant la lettre, that he was not a Right-Wing Authoritarian. The Youth Culture today may (or may not; I am no longer a member) have identified this group and named them “haters.” If they have, the name will not be appreciated.

RWAs are found everywhere, but some professions attract them more than others. They tend to be fairly common among policemen (I’ve found). Altemeyer says:


“Compared with others, authoritarians have not spent much time examining evidence, thinking critically, reaching independent conclusions, and seeing whether their conclusions mesh with the other things they believe. Instead, they have largely accepted what they were told by the authorities in their lives, which leaves them time for other things, but which also leaves them unpracticed in thinking for themselves.” “There was virtually nothing about themselves Highs [high-scoring RWAs] were unwilling to face and deal with, according to them. Yet when we told some High RWAs they were low in self-esteem, and that this had serious implications for their future, a lot of authoritarians fled from the news, not even checking to see if it was correct. And many Highs told us, point blank, that if it turned out they were more prejudiced than average, they did not want to be told.”


RWAs are good at ignoring what they don’t want to know, although this probably does not indicate anything about Chomsky. If you find you’re dealing with someone who just doesn’t want to know anything about 9/11 Truth, suspect an RWA. RWAs don’t need to learn anything about 9/11 Truth, because they know everything already. At least this appears to be the case at this stage of Truth’s disclosure. When it is more widely disseminated and deeply accepted, that may change. What will not change is their attitude to learning about themselves.

The sheer hatred shown by the counter demonstrators and video makers who oppose the NY 9/11 Truth group indicates that these individuals are RWAs who have acquired a small degree of Truth knowledge. Right-Wing Authoritarianism’s third component probably explains the opposition of such organizations as CSICOP to 9/11 Truth.

Remember that a great proportion of Truthers started out by trying to refute the evidence they were exposed to, and that Bill Christison spent “the better part of the last five years” opposing 9/11 Truth before he decided to find out what he was opposing. If and when RWAs come to believe their authorities have betrayed them, those authorities have no greater enemies. The field of salesmanship is full of rules-of-thumb. One of them is: it takes eight contacts to make a sale. Another is: when prospects avoid you it is out of fear, because they know you can sell them.

In general, but perhaps not invariably, RWAs flee or avoid 9/11 Truth information, those in denial repress or disbelieve it.

‘All day long we unconsciously selectively perceive the world about us. Man can prevent unpleasant perceptions by varying his attention and by wishful perceiving or thinking. Unconscious distortion of perception of external stimuli that arouse unpleasant emotions is called denial.”
“The American people know what they saw with their own eyes on September 11, 2001,” says Defense Secretary Gates. And both to Peter Jennings and to Dan Rather, it was so clear that the World Trade Center was being demolished by explosives that they blurted out that thought at the time.

In the 1950s a psychology professor, Solomon Asch, did some experiments on college students. He told them that he wanted to test visual perception, but that was a lie. He had them sit in a classroom with other students and showed them all some lines, asking which lines looked like they were the same length, but only one student was being tested at a time. The others were conspirators along with Professor Asch, and they deliberately gave wrong answers. The student being tested was always asked last, after having heard all the others say that it looked to them as though the wrong lines were the same length. The experiment was really to find out how many people, percentagewise, could be made to say that they saw what they didn’t see, just to go along with the crowd. The answer was: about one third. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Asch_conformity_experiments

A college classroom is a relatively benign environment, at least compared to the situation that Winston Smith, the protagonist of 1984, found himself in. “ ‘Do you remember,’ he went on, ‘writing in your diary, “Freedom is the freedom to say that two plus two make four’?” ’ ‘Yes,’ said Winston. O’Brien held up his left hand, its back towards Winston, with the thumb hidden and the four fingers extended. ‘How many fingers am I holding up, Winston?’ ‘Four.’ ‘And if the Party says that it is not four but five -- then how many?’ ”

How much the students believed what they said is probably unknowable, but the willingness to deny what is in front of your face is certainly something worthy of being noted. Mr. Lev Grossman says, “Granted, the Pentagon crash site looks odd in photographs,” but the fact hardly slows him down. “Loose Change [sic] appeals to the viewer’s common sense: it tells you to forget the official explanations and the expert testimony, and trust your eyes and your brain instead. It implies that the world can be grasped by laymen without any help or interference from the talking heads.” Or the other students, or the Party‘s officials and experts, functioning as designated “authorities.”

This sort of resistance may be the most deep-seated of all. When someone brags, “I saw Loose Change. Didn’t convince me,” or goes through all the material you give them and only comments, “Interesting,” and then changes the subject, you are dealing with something other than a psychological trait like Right-Wing Authoritarianism. You are dealing with a common human failing which cuts across familiar political divides, and which is just as likely to be found among progressives as among others. There really are people who, as Jack Nicholson said, just can’t handle the truth. If this is seen as discouraging, it shouldn’t be. It shows that the ability to call a spade a spade is not a progressive monopoly.

In the Q & A session after his videotaped lecture, 9/11: The Myth and the Reality, David Ray Griffin says that he has a “theological friend” who finds the evidence for 9/11 Truth “convincing,” but nevertheless “refuses” to believe it. The word ‘demonstration’ has roots in the idea of making something visible, quite literally, to the eyes. If you are dealing with a sighted person who simply refuses to admit what is in front of their face, perhaps sometimes the appropriate response is simply a gentle, “Shame on you.”

In Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions, Jaakko Hintikka discusses, “…among other things, Moore’s famous problem of ’saying and disbelieving’: Why is the sentence ‘p but I do not believe that p’ absurd to utter?” Following Moore, he points out that the sentence is not inconsistent with itself. He speaks on page 23 of being “inconsistent for you.” His response is to add the notion of “indefensibility” to that of inconsistency. “The general characteristic of indefensible statements is, therefore, that they depend for their truth on somebody’s failure (past, present, or future) to follow the implications of what he knows far enough.” (p. 32). At the time when Moore and Hintikka addressed such matters it could reasonably be doubted whether the phenomenon of indefensible statements like ‘p but I do not believe that p’ was common enough to merit really serious investigation. September 11, 2001 changed that.

“Unconscious distortion of perception” may manifest as “failure to follow the implications of what one knows.” Whatever proposition p may be, p certainly implies p, but it seems that the psychological phenomenon of denial can prevent following even that implication.

About Griffin’s theological friend, one wonders what his theological opinion is of Sartre’s conception of bad faith.

I think it is likely to be a waste of time to discuss 9/11 with Mr. Grossman, or with anyone else who is so desperately frightened by the facts, or by the possibility of being in a minority, that he cannot admit what is in front of his face.

Talking with people in denial, whether they are followers of Alexander Cockburn or of Rush Limbaugh, should be done with sensitivity to the individual. It is a cruel thing to take away someone’s blankie. Parental discretion is advised.

An interesting phenomenon is the cooperation of RWAs and those in denial. At this stage of the game, some RWAs need some small justification for ignoring 9/11 Truth, and those in denial can provide that by dealing with the evidence for them and pronouncing it “not credible.” A fine example is represented by the BBC‘s anti-Truth video, made by Mr. Guy Smith. Listening to Mr. Smith speaking with Alex Jones about 9/11 Truth, it is clear that Mr. Smith is in denial, and that he would not have undertaken the project without encouragement from someone else. The video can now serve, along with other projects such as the NIST Report and the 9/11 Commission Report itself, as additional justification for avoidance. RWAs are unlikely to spend time on NIST or the Commission, and the time it takes to see a video should satisfy their consciences that they now know all they need to know.

Just as the ability to face, or admit, unpalatable facts cuts across left/right dichotomies, the fourth category of resistance is orthogonal to the first three, since it is an occupational category rather than a psychological one. The vast majority of Washington politicians are keenly aware that they could never make as much money doing anything else, and they are quite interested in hanging onto, or even upgrading, their six-figure sinecures. It’s not that they are averse to doing what’s right, it’s that they are inclined to do what’s right for them. Their real opinions are probably unknowable, and even if they could be known, would be of no practical importance. If their salaries were set at $30,000 a year, they would have an opportunity to demonstrate that they really are as civic-minded as they say they are. We must make it possible for them, and help them, to do the right thing.

Politicians are a subset of those whose opinions are influenced by the way they make their living. There are plenty of government, defense contractor, and other employees, who get no direct benefit from 9/11, but who pay the familiar price of telling conscious lies simply in order to keep their jobs. Of course, there is a sliding scale of persuasion: job, freedom, life. Something for everyone.

The segment of the public we should concentrate on trying to reach is neither in denial nor fleeing from 9/11 Truth nor primarily interested in which way the wind is blowing. Rather than saying, like the authoritarian, “I don’t need to learn about that stuff. I know everything already,” it simply says, “Hey, just let me live my life. OK?” The resistance of the RWA and the person in denial is directed against 9/11 Truth specifically, because of its unpleasantness. The great mass of resistance we face is simply that of the great mass of the peoplewhat Ferejohn calls “most of us”who are used to having others handle the disagreeable business of politics for them. Most of them are what used to be called “wage slaves.” They are the prize we’re after. Joe Six-pack may say, “It’s not my business” now, but when he finds out about 9/11 Truth, he will make it his business.































II: Types of Knowledge


Just as knowing about sources of resistance can be helpful, so can knowing about different types of knowledge, and the sorts of messages which are appropriate when trying to create them. The principal distinction we are concerned with is the distinction between the knowledge that individuals have and the knowledge that groups, as groups, have.

Since we are knowledge workers, it behooves us to know something about how people come to believe what they do believe. Beginning with the study of individual knowledge, an excellent place to start learning about that is Keith Devlin‘s book, quoted above.

Devlin, nothing if not helpful, summarizes his book thus: “…if I had to distill from our investigations a single slogan that, if followed, would have the greatest positive impact on information managementpersonal or in businessI would have no difficulty. It’s this: Context matters.” (p. 199).
The first part of Devlin’s book may strike you as rather abstract and remote from our concerns, but the second part will show you why the effort was worth it. As he says, “…there is nothing as practical as a good theory.” (p. 206).

“…a conversation between two individuals may be regarded as a process whereby they cooperate to add information to a common pool. … The name linguists give to the common information pool for a conversation…is the ‘common ground’ for the conversation.” (p. 86).

Three

“…key contextsthe background situations, the common ground, and the focal situationare regions of what we might call information space. … The purpose of a meeting [or a contact] can be regarded as the movement of items in the different background situations into the common ground. Such movement is caused by the participants jointly visiting that item in information space. A participant may take information within her own background and, by making a successful contribution to the conversation, put it into the common ground. (Making a statement that the others accept is an example of such a contribution.} Or she may use her words…to get another participant to take information from his background and put it into the common ground. (Successfully asking a question is an example.}” (pp.207f).
“The concepts of background and common ground are analysts’ inventions. In fact, it is misleading to think of the background and common-ground situations as cleanly delineated regions separated by a clear border.” (p. 90).
“…going from a two-person conversation to a conversation involving three or more people is so significant it is probably misleading to continue to use the same word ‘conversation’.” (p. 113).


Devlin provides diagrams of conversations involving both two and three persons, and shows that for three people, “Already the diagram is too complex to understand easily, and yet I have left off the focal situation.” Though activists as such certainly engage in two-person conversations, their main efforts are directed to much larger audiences. If the case of N = 3 is barely manageable, what can be made of the case where N = ~300,000,000?

Clearly, thoughts of a diagram are out of place here, and yet the ideas of background and common ground are still reasonably distinct and may be usable. Social scientists, especially political scientists, are used to dealing with such “conversations,” and their methods and approaches may be a propos. “…the common ground consists of common knowledge…”

The worst danger the 9/11 Truth Movement faces is that of becoming an accepted, inert part of the public consciousness, allowed to exist in its own niche in public discourse in an encapsulated way, just as other minority opinions are tolerated so long as they threaten no conceivable imminent change. This is how the truth of the JFK assassination was contained. Even antiestablishment majority opinions can safely be tolerated as “open secrets.”

Surveys conducted by Louis Harris and Associates in 1967, 1975 and 1981 showed that about two-thirds of the people in the United States thought that the assassination of President Kennedy was part of a conspiracy, and in 2003 Fox News had Opinion Dynamics Corporation conduct a poll of 900 registered voters nationwide. With a margin of error of ±3 percentage points, 66% believed the assassination was the act of a conspiracy. This is a big enough majority to override a presidential veto. “Despite a majority believing there was a cover-up, there is widespread agreement that no additional inquiries should be done — 74 percent say the government should not conduct another investigation into the assassination, compared to 20 percent who think it should.”
http://www.foxnews.com/printer_friendly_story/0,3566,102511,00.html

Everyone knows that O.J. Simpson is a murderer. And everyone knows that everyone knows it. Chuck Barris claims to have been a paid murderer for the CIA. The CIA did not vet his book, nor did he ask them to, as far as I am aware, nor did he suffer any unwanted consequences of his confession. In fact he may, like other murderers, have made more money from the confession than he did from the murders. Why? Simply because, although the information is as public as anyone could want, no one, (that is to say, not enough people) believes it, believes it enough, or realizes that (enough) other people believe it or will admit to believing it.

What exactly is an “open secret?”

The change we seek cannot be brought about by any one person. It must be accomplished by collective action. We seek to convey information not just to individuals, but to a large enough group. We seek to instill not just individual knowledge, but common knowledge.

One naturally assumes that if a person knows something, they know that they know it. One is tempted analogously, but falsely, to assume that if a group knows something, the group knows that it knows it. In fact, each one of the group may falsely believe that they are the only ones in the group holding the opinion.

In 1924 Floyd H. Allport broached the idea of what is now called pluralistic ignorance.
Because the early date makes his observations so instructive, I shall quote him at length.

“Psychologically speaking, ‘the public’ means to an individual an imagined crowd in which (as he believes) certain opinions, feelings, and overt reactions are universal. What these responses are imagined to be is determined by the press, by rumor, and by social projection. Impressed by some bit of public propaganda, the individual assumes that the impression created is universal and therefore of vital consequence. Thus the impression of universality is exploited and commercialized both on the rostrum and in the daily press. Newspaper columns abound in such statements as “it is the consensus of opinion here,” “telegrams [of remonstrance or petition] are pouring in from all sides,” “widespread amazement was felt,” and the like.
During a recent visit of General Pershing to Boston there appeared a newspaper article inspired, perhaps, by a discontented faction of World War veterans. The following quotation will show the attempt of its author to magnify the personal grievance to one of civic interest. (Italics are by the present writer.)

The controversy which has been raging since the refusal of certain YD leaders to attend the mayor’s banquet at the  this evening [30 out of 300 invited refused to come] has accentuated interest in the general’s coming, and Boston is perhaps more concerned over the character of the reception accorded him than in whatever he may do or say while here.

The reader who is not on his guard is likely to be seriously misled by journalism of this character. The allusion to the ‘concern’ of large numbers produces an unthinking belief in the importance of the statements made. The artifice, however, seems obvious enough when we pause to inquire how the reporter could possibly have known what Boston as a whole was ‘concerned over.’
The same deception lurks in flaring headlines. Our eye is caught by these ‘scare-heads,’ and we say to ourselves unconsciously: “This is big news: it is printed large to attract universal attention. Hence everyone else is looking at it as I am doing. That which everybody is interested in must be of great importance.” And we proceed, ready to be duly impressed with what follows. Newspapers which capitalize the illusion of universality in this way unfortunately have little to say that is fit to read. But the unscrupulous and sensation-hunting journalist has scored in securing attention and in controlling a portion of public opinion through social projection and the illusion of universality.”

Robert K. Merton describes the above as speaking of

“…one form of what Floyd H. Allport described as ‘pluralistic ignorance,’ that is, the pattern in which individual members of a group assume that they are virtually alone in holding the social attitudes and expectations they do, all unknowing that others privately share them. This is a frequently observed condition of a group which is so organized that mutual observability among its members is slight. This basic notion of pluralistic ignorance can, however, be usefully enlarged to take account of a formally similar but substantively different condition. This is the condition now under review, in which the members of a role-set do not know that their expectations of the behavior appropriate for the occupants of a particular status are different from those held by other members of the role-set. … .In some instances, the replacing of pluralistic ignorance by common knowledge serves to make for a re-definition of what can properly be expected of the status-occupant.”

Whether or not this is a generalization of Allport is of relatively little consequence. Merton seems to have coined the phrase ‘pluralistic ignorance’ himself. As the expression is used now, a group’s ignorance of what that group’s opinion really is constitutes pluralistic ignorance.

No polls have ever been taken to determine what the public believes about what most people believe about the Kennedy assassination.

Though pluralistic ignorance was first introduced via the thought of a newspaper’s readership, it has tended to be studied in relatively small groupsneighbors, for examplewhere its existence tends to be surprising. If one thinks instead of really large publicscities, or nationsits existence is not so surprising, because no individual can be linked to or connected with a majority of such a large group except through some medium; hence, the term “mass media.” If the private owners of such media wish to shade things to convey a false impression, nothing prevents them. They are not under oath, and apart from that there is no law against lying. They take pains to create the impression that they are subject to some sort of official sanction for dishonesty, and like to tell us how “trusted” they are, but they never hint that perhaps they will be sanctioned for telling the truth. They operate on a for-profit basis. If most of the time they wish to convey the impression that, say, the opinion that there was a Kennedy conspiracy is the opinion of a disreputable minority, they certainly can. (And they certainly do.) As this example illustrates, pluralistic ignorance is fairly easy for the media to create, and it is a very valuable tool.

It is valuable because of what Elisabeth Noelle-Neumann dubbed “the spiral of silence” in her 1984 book of that name. The spiral of silence describes how the perception of public opinion influences the willingness of individuals to express their own opinions, when they believe those opinions are a minority view. According to her, people have a sort of “sense” of what majority opinion is, and fear being isolated. The perception of public opinion thus acts as a sort of control on the expression of opinion. Whether such a “sense” explains anything not explicable through the existence of the mass media is debatable, but because the effect is real whatever causes it, control over perception of what the majority opinion is, is obviously a powerful weapon in the information war. Had the public been aware that most people were with them in thinking as they did, would they have been so willing to let the Kennedy murderers get away with it?
http://www.12manage.com/methods_noelle-neumann_spiral_of_silence.html

What all this tells us is that it is not enough to contact and convince people. We must interest the politically uninterested, if only briefly, we must do it without the mass media, at least initially, and we must let everyone know that everyone else knows.

All through the Vietnam War, the mass media told us that although those grisly images might seem discouraging, there was light at the end of the tunnel, and the U.S. was “winning.” However, there are limits even to spin, and when the U.S. withdrew the media could not hide that fact. It will be interesting to see how they spin their own complicity in deception when the worms finally turn.

The opposite of pluralistic ignorance is the idiomatically-misnamed notion of common knowledge (it is sometimes, and better, called mutual knowledge, but ‘common knowledge‘ has become entrenched). If something is common knowledge in the relevant sense, then not only does everyone know it, but everyone knows that everyone knows it, and everyone knows that everyone knows that everyone knows it, etc. This characterization leaves many important questions unsettled. Must the individuals actually realize that they know that they know… an infinite number of times, or is it enough to know something which entails that they know that they know…; or that they know that they know something which entails that they know that they know…? Must the knowing all take place at the same time? “Evidence suggests that knowledge of other people’s knowledge takes longer to form than knowledge.” Must each individual know each other individual, or can you know that everyone knows without knowing everyone? What about “almost everyone?” What if we substitute belief for knowledge? Answering all these questions is not necessary for our purpose here; i.e., we need not define common knowledge as precisely as would be appropriate on a different occasion. We may take it here to be simply the absence of pluralistic ignorance.
In his article on “Common Knowledge” in the online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Peter Vanderschraaf says, “The analysis and applications of…multi-agent knowledge concepts has become a lively field of research,”
http://plato.stanford.edu/search/searcher.py?query+Common+Knowledge

Under the name “common knowledge,” the subject is usually given a more or less mathematical treatment, and appears in more or less mathematical contexts, but it has broad literary roots in R.D. Laing and David Cooper, Pirandello, and even, according to Laing and Russell Jacoby, in Feuerbach.

A notion of common knowledge is common to the study both of multi-agent knowledge and of individual knowledge. If A knows that B knows that A knows…that p, that is individual knowledge that A has. It is also individual knowledge that B has. It just so happens that the content of this individual knowledge entails that more than one individual has it.

It seems appropriate to think of common knowledge as a dimension, or a direction in which one can travel. Some notion of common knowledge might serve as an “explication” of Dr. John McMurtry’s conception (in 9/11 and American Empire, Vol. I: Intellectuals Speak Out) of a “group-mind.” The group-mind’s self-awareness will consist of common knowledge among the minds that compose it. The Marxian notion of “class consciousness” suggests itself here.
Observe the difference between between simply disseminating knowledge as widely as possible, and making it common knowledge.

Elections are recently over. By far most political signs I saw simply had a candidate’s name on them, or such a message as “Vote for Joe.” What reasons did they give me to vote for Joe? None. Nada. Zip. Zilch. They made no risky claims for Joe which his rivals could conceivably show to be false, because they didn’t say anything at all about him. In fact, I can’t remember any that did. Isn’t this sort of advertising nonsensical? It’s not disseminating anything about Joe beyond the bare fact that he’s running, and that his name is Joe. Or is it? How many such signs I see gives me an idea of how much money his campaign has. That may persuade others to think that if he has so very much money, there must be a lot of people supporting him. It is at least not ludicrous, not out-of-the-question, for Joe to hold the office. He is a “credible” candidate. When money talks, what does it say? Very little, in fact, but what little it does say becomes, and is intended to become, common knowledge.

Contrast this situation with a reasoned presentation of the case for Joe’s being a better holder of the office than the other candidates. The more reasons presented, the more the case can be disputed by denying the factuality of those reasons. The more reasons presented, the more voluminous, specific and detailed the information becomes; and the more voluminous, specific and detailed the information becomes the less likely it is all to become common knowledge. Instead, if the various claims are disputed, what becomes common knowledge is the putative fact that Joe’s qualifications are controversial, i.e., subject to being controverted.

We must distinguish between simply spreading knowledge and making something common knowledge, simply because of the tension, the trade-off, between them. Michael Suk-Young Chwe marks the distinction by means of the terminology of content vs. publicity.

There is a limit to how much content can become common knowledge, first, because there is a limit on individual knowledge. One can’t be a doctor and a lawyer and a mathematician, and a philosopher, and a physicist, and a mechanical engineer, and a theologian, and a pilot, and have, as Alex Jones puts it, a Master’s in 9/11.

But the limitations on common knowledge are much more severe than on individuals’ knowledge simply because the more recently acquired or specific a piece of knowledge is, the more doubtful it becomes that it is common knowledge, or ever can become common knowledge. Common knowledge exists in the social structures of primates and in the hunting parties of carnivores, and needless to say, what is common knowledge in these cases isn‘t, by human standards, terribly complex.

“…we can assume that because of the division of labor role-specific knowledge will grow at a faster rate than generally relevant and accessible knowledge.”

Even in a society composed of people each of whom had all the above qualifications, there would be plenty of room for individuals’ doubts about other individuals’ knowledge. But having more content more widely disseminated results in somewhat more specific common knowledge. A more-highly-educated population will have more-specific common knowledge.

Does anyone think that the purpose of having a 9/11 Truther interviewed by some broadcasting Brownshirt is the dissemination of content? Of course not. The idea is rather to spread the simple impression that it’s open season on such heretics and that they are publicly-designated targets.

There is no question of content being “better” than publicity, or vice versa. In different situations and for different audiences, one is more appropriate, the other less so. Different strokes for different folks. Rather than the Movement as a whole leaning toward one direction or the other; we should think full-spectrum dominance. There is room for everyone’s contribution. That said, I think we would agree that up to now more has been done on content, on technical research, than on publicity, perhaps under the naive assumption that truth is bound to make itself known.

The Truth Movement is unlike the Peace Movement, the Civil Rights Movement, the Gay Rights Movement, the Evironmental Movement, the Feminist Movement, and every other Movement I can think of in that it is much more content-based than publicity-based. Everyone knows that war is bad, but some people feel it is now necessary. The Peace Movement has nothing new to actually tell them, other than, “WE feel it’s NOT necessary.” Other Movements all carry with them some relatively new information, but the 9/11 Truth Movement consists almost entirely of new information, information that will change people’s behavior when they acquire it, and this fact tends to make us concentrate on developing content, sometimes at the expense of publicity.

“Something will happen when enough of us know,” concludes that masterpiece video, 911 Mysteries: Part One. This is almost right. Of course, one can always take it to be true by definition: if nothing happens, that’s not enough of us. But what is important is not only that enough of us know, but that we are aware that we know, and that we are aware that there are enough of us; that we are, in a way, “on the same page,” or “together.”

It seems that RWAs will be more affected by individual knowledge; those in denial, whether on the Left or Right, will be more affected by common knowledge. If it seems you are dealing with someone amenable to reason, use content; the specific knowledge that constitutes our background knowledge as Truthers. If you are dealing with someone in denial, only an increase in society’s knowledge of 9/11 Truth will move them toward more comfort in admitting the obvious. Do not address them as individuals. They are reachable not through content, but through publicity.

Assuming therefore that we are addressing people not in denial, we must reckon with the problem of time. We must present something, a piece of content, that is graspable quickly enough to capture someone’s interest, to convince them, not of 9/11 Truth, but that the subject of 9/11 Truth is worth looking into. We must present the most concentrated and hard-to-argue-with smoking gun (or guns) possible.

Continuing in terms of Devlin‘s “information space,” if we think of multi-agent “common knowledge” as corresponding to the familiar four-dimensional world of daily life, individual knowledge- or belief-concepts correspond to the extra “hidden” or “compactified” dimensions of twenty-first century physics. Which is more important or “real” depends on your interests. The common pool of information created in a two-person conversation is through common knowledge located in both heads; in a many-person conversation, or interaction, the “group-mind” created is located in each of them.

The “background” knowledge of the 9/11 Truth Movement is simply what we know that the public doesn’t. It is what we are trying to put into the common ground. If we think of “the public” as our conversational partner, what is that partner putting into the common ground out of its background? Who are, or what is, the public? Who should we take as being the public?

It makes a big difference whether we think of that partner as speaking to us through the mass media or not, and it makes a big difference whether we think of the common ground as simply the content of those mass media, as there is a tendency to do. That tendency should be resisted.

Beside verbally putting facts into the common ground, Devlin discloses that you can also physically put artifacts into it.

“One common and potentially effective strategy is to make regular notes on a whiteboard or a display pad as the meeting proceeds. … An analyst would say that the whiteboard is an example of a common artifact. Common artifacts provide information in such a way that it readily becomes common knowledge to everybody having simultaneous access to it. The whiteboard provides common knowledge because it is a public display, and thus everyone in the room can see one another looking at the board.
The use of a whiteboard is quite different from everyone in the room taking their own notes. You and I may see each other taking notes, but as the meeting proceeds, I cannot be sure what notes you have taken and you won’t know what I have written. So, even though we may have taken the same notes, the information in our notes is not automatically common knowledgethat is, writing information in our individual notebooks does not make it common knowledge, as happens when that information is written on a whiteboard. This is the key distinction between a common artifact and a private source of information.”


As far as concerns our search for the most concentrated and hard-to-argue-with smoking gun possible, this is good news. What sort of artifact would be especially relevant to 9/11 Truth? To answer that question let us look at another book, this one by Fred I. Dretske, viz., Knowledge and the Flow of Information, (Cambridge, MA, 1982). He says:


“…consider the difference between a picture and a statement. Suppose a cup has coffee in it, and we want to communicate this piece of information. If I simply tell you, ’The cup has coffee in it,’ this (acoustic) signal carries the information that the cup has coffee in it in digital form. No more specific information is supplied about the cup (or the coffee) than that there is some coffee in the cup. You are not told how much coffee there is in the cup, how large the cup is, how dark the coffee is, what the shape and orientation of the cup are, and so on. If, on the other hand, I photograph the scene and show you the picture, the information that the cup has coffee in it is conveyed in analog form. The picture tells you that there is some coffee in the cup by telling you, roughly, how much coffee is in the cup, the shape, size, and color of the cup, and so on.
I can say that A and B are of different size without saying how much they differ in size or which is larger, but I cannot picture A and B as being of different size without picturing one of them as larger and indicating, roughly, how much larger it is. …
To say that a picture is worth a thousand words is merely to acknowledge that, for most pictures at least, the sentence needed to express all the information contained in the picture would have to be very complex indeed. Most pictures have a wealth of detail, and a degree of specificity, that makes it all but impossible to provide even an approximate linguistic rendition of the information the picture carries in digital form.”

How many time-wasting arguments about what happened to the Towers would be obviated if they were conducted with constant reference to a picture? Why do you think the media avoid pictures so assiduously? We need to put as many pictures before the public’s eyes as possible, accompanied by a small amount of text to lead the viewer as quickly as possible to the relevant features. In that way we address both the right and left hemispheres.

We also need to take account of Lakoff’s thinking on reframing. A tiny word can make a massive difference. Do not accept the description of the Towers as “falling down.” They FELL APART (according to the Administration). We don’t have “theories.” Some individuals in the Movement have “theories.” What we have are pictures.

The fact that there are people, and more than a few of them, who are willing to deny that they see what they do see has been used to frame discussion of 9/11 Truth as “controversial,” when in fact it is no such thing. Lakoff points out that it is a mistake for progressives to concede to their opponents such framing as the phrase “tax relief.” I believe it is just as much a mistake for Truthers to concede that 9/11 Truth is controversial. The fact that someone denies that 2+2=4 does not make arithmetic a controversial subject, but the reputation of being “controversial” is used to deter people from looking into 9/11 Truth, by making them think, as Chomsky thinks, that the result will not be worth the effort.

We need to address rational others in something like the following terms:

When something falls, it falls in one direction. When something explodes, it explodes in all directions. Which did the Towers do? When something falls, it falls down, not up and not sideways. [Look at these pictures.] When an object collapses, it breaks into two or a few pieces. It does not break everywhere. The Towers were not made of sand, they were made of steel and concrete, and yet in a matter of seconds they dissolved from the top down like sand castles. Nothing “collapses” to dust. Steel doesn’t break, it bends; but it can be cut by oxyacetylene torches and the cutting charges used in controlled demolitions. Since innumerable sections of steel columns in the Towers were found in clean-edged pieces, were they instantly cut by oxyacetylene torches or by explosives? What sent them flying in all directions? Does a building that is simply falling down normally produce shrapnel? When a building falls on a human body, that body is crushed where it is. It is not turned to fragments of bone, which are then found on the roofs of other buildings. All these things are not controversial; they’re obvious. How do you knock down three buildings with two airplanes? What mental contortion will you not attempt, and what intellectual crucifixion will you not submit to, in order to have your dinner undisturbed?

Now let’s proceed to multi-agent information, and in particular to common knowledge. What Devlin’s book is to individual information, Michael Chwe’s book, Rational Ritual: Culture, Coordination and Common Knowledge, (Princeton, 2001) is to multi-agent information (that is to say, indispensable). Its bibliography alone is worth the price of the book. Chwe’s book can be described thus: “game theory finds culture.” (p. 99). Though apparently a strictly academic work, it is full of practical information for activists.

Chwe says: “The best common knowledge generator in the United States is the Super Bowl…” I don’t think there ever will be a 9/11 Truth advertisement displayed during that event, so let’s see what else he’s got. He notes that in the French Revolution much use was made of “festivals,…and even planting liberty trees and wearing revolutionary colors.” As pictures are powerful tools in spreading individual knowledge, or content, gear and ritual (i.e., spectacle) are powerful in propagating common knowledge, or publicity. The Revolutionary tricolour echoes in the recent Color Revolutions of Central and Eastern Europe, and Central Asia. We should try to “be the media” by using unmistakable logos wherever possible, and, in general, being as visible as possible. In Evgeny Zamiatin’s We, the inspiration for Orwell’s 1984, the revolutionaries recruited and struggled simply by making their name, the Mephi, as widely seen as possible. We should emphasize our common opposition to the lie, not our individually incompatible versions of the truth.



Appendix: On Knowledge by Consensus


You are here because you have failed in humility, in self-discipline. You would not make the act of submission which is the price of sanity. You preferred to be a lunatic, a minority of one. Only the disciplined mind can see reality, Winston. You believe that reality is something objective, external, existing in its own right. You also believe that the nature of reality is self-evident. When you delude yourself into thinking that you see something, you assume that everyone else sees the same thing as you. But I tell you, Winston, that reality is not external. Reality exists in the human mind, and nowhere else. Not in the individual mind, which can make mistakes, and in any case soon perishes: only in the mind of the Party, which is collective and immortal. Whatever the Party holds to be the truth, is truth. It is impossible to see reality except by looking through the eyes of the Party. That is the fact that you have got to relearn, Winston. It needs an act of self-destruction, an effort of the will. You must humble yourself before you can become sane.”
He paused for a few moments, as though to allow what he had been saying to sink in.
“Do you remember,” he went on, “writing in your diary, ‘Freedom is the freedom to say that two plus two make four’?”
“Yes,” said Winston.
O’Brien held up his left hand, its back towards Winston, with the thumb hidden and the four fingers extended.
“How many fingers am I holding up, Winston?”
“Four.”
“And if the party says that it is not four but five -- then how many?”
“Four.”
The word ended in a gasp of pain. The needle of the dial had shot up to fifty-five. The sweat had sprung out all over Winston’s body. The air tore into his lungs and issued again in deep groans which even by clenching his teeth he could not stop. O’Brien watched him, the four fingers still extended. He drew back the lever. This time the pain was only slightly eased.
“How many fingers, Winston?”
“Four.”
The needle went up to sixty.
“How many fingers, Winston?”
“Four! Four! What else can I say? Four!”
The needle must have risen again, but he did not look at it. The heavy, stern face and the four fingers filled his vision. The fingers stood up before his eyes like pillars, enormous, blurry, and seeming to vibrate, but unmistakably four.
“How many fingers, Winston?”
“Four! Stop it, stop it! How can you go on? Four! Four!”
“How many fingers, Winston?”
“Five! Five! Five!”
“No, Winston, that is no use. You are lying. You still think there are four. How many fingers, please?”
“Four! Five! Four! Anything you like. Only stop it, stop the pain!”
Abruptly he was sitting up with O’Brien’s arm round his shoulders. He had perhaps lost consciousness for a few seconds. The bonds that had held his body down were loosened. He felt very cold, he was shaking uncontrollably, his teeth were chattering, the tears were rolling down his cheeks. For a moment he clung to O’Brien like a baby, curiously comforted by the heavy arm round his shoulders. He had the feeling that O’Brien was his protector, that the pain was something that came from outside, from some other source, and that it was O’Brien who would save him from it.
“You are a slow learner, Winston,” said O’Brien gently.
“How can I help it?” he blubbered. “How can I help seeing what is in front of my eyes? Two and two are four.”
“Sometimes, Winston. Sometimes they are five. Sometimes they are three. Sometimes they are all of them at once. You must try harder. It is not easy to become sane.”





October 17, 2004
Megalomania in the White House
Posted by Adam Young at October 17, 2004 02:53 PM
In the summer of 2002, after I had written an article in Esquire that the White House didn't like about Bush's former communications director, Karen Hughes, I had a meeting with a senior adviser to Bush. He expressed the White House's displeasure, and then he told me something that at the time I didn't fully comprehend -- but which I now believe gets to the very heart of the Bush presidency.
The aide said that guys like me were ''in what we call the reality-based community,'' which he defined as people who ''believe that solutions emerge from your judicious study of discernible reality.'' I nodded and murmured something about enlightenment principles and empiricism. He cut me off. ''That's not the way the world really works anymore,'' he continued. ''We're an empire now, and when we act, we create our own reality. And while you're studying that reality -- judiciously, as you will -- we'll act again, creating other new realities, which you can study too, and that's how things will sort out. We're history's actors . . . and you, all of you, will be left to just study what we do.''

http://blog.lewrockwell.com/lewrw/archives/006267.html